13. Augustine on God and Eternal Truth
In his dialogue On Free Choice of the Will (Macmillan, 1964), St. Augustine (354-430 C.E.) argues that our minds can know truths that are eternal. For Augustine, something is eternal if it exists in a timeless, unchanging state. So eternal truths are unchanging and are not in, or influenced by, time. For example, consider the following three propositions:
- 2+2=4
- A cannot be both B and not B at the same time and the same respect (the law of non-contradiction)
- Either A or not A (the law of excluded middle)
Augustine would claim that these propositions are eternal truths. This means their truth never changes and is not dependent on any event in the past, present, or future. These truths hold for everyone, everywhere, at all times. To be sure, changing beings can think these truths in time and they can be represented in various languages and sentences that change. But the truths themselves never change.
Now ask yourself: could human minds produce eternal truths? Well, if eternal truth exists then it is unchanging. But human minds are always changing. So eternal truth cannot be a product of our minds. Augustine writes: “If truth were equal to our minds, it would be subject to change. Our minds sometimes see more and sometimes less, and because of this we acknowledge that they are mutable. Truth, remaining in itself, does not gain anything when we see it, or lose anything when we do not see it” (67). We could also add that there was a time when humans did not exist. So eternal truths, as always existing, cannot possibility be the product of our minds. But if human minds didn’t produce eternal truth then what did? Well, nothing produces eternal truth because, being eternal, it always exists. But perhaps some mind, rather than producing eternal truths, always has eternal truths in mind. Such a mind would have to be eternal itself if the truths it possesses are eternal. Augustine thinks this line of reasoning strongly suggests an eternal being exists who sustains eternal truths. He writes:
“You granted, moreover, that if I showed you something higher than our minds, you would admit, assuming that nothing existed which was still higher, that God exists. I accepted your condition and said that it was enough to show this. For if there is something more excellent than truth, this is God. If there is not, then truth itself is God. Whether or not truth is God, you cannot deny that God exists, and this was the question with which we agreed to deal.” (71)
So the argument of the dialogue is as follows:
Premise 1: If there is something unchanging and not created by human minds, then God exists.
Premise 2: Truth is unchanging and not created by human minds.
Therefore, God exists.
Of course this argument, while fascinating, leaves a bit to be desired if we are hoping for an argument that demonstrates, among other things, one personal God that would be akin to the God of the monotheistic faiths. Perhaps this is to be expected since Augustine’s argument is presented in a dialogue format which, far from being dogmatic, helps generate inquiry. He himself notes that his arguments are “sure yet tenuous” (71). Nonetheless, we can ask: why one God? Why a personal God who is all loving? Why would this God be omnipotent and omniscient? And why couldn’t we argue that the eternal truths we are able to think are really just abstract entities, like numbers, that don’t exist in a mind at all? After all, it is often argued that one of Augustine’s influences, Plato, argued just that. So there are some serious questions that need to be addressed. But I think plausible answers are available if we supplement Augustine’s general argumentative strategy in various ways. Perhaps, as Leibniz argued, the integration of truth is a way to show how truth cannot be grounded in many beings but requires one. Perhaps, if truth is predicated of propositions, and propositions are intentional mental states, then the being that has these truths would indeed be a mind of some sort. And if we require a necessarily existing being to ground necessarily existing truths, then we might argue that such a being would be totally independent and fully actual with no potentials at all. This would, in turn, help us see how, on the one hand, this being would lack nothing and, on the other hand, how it would be unique. I explore these approaches and many others in my own Augustine-inspired divine conceptualist argument for God’s existence here.
For Augustine’s related account of divine illumination, which is an account of how we come to know eternal truths, go here.
For Leibniz’s account of God and eternal truth, go here.
…big help..thankyou…
Thank you very much, very succinct
You’re welcome! Thanks for reading. If you get a chance, check out my divine conceptualist argument for God’s existence which builds on Augustine’s vision.
Thank you very much for such a brilliant write up. I am a philosophy student who will like to learn more from you